Highlights
- Social justice is certainly a vexed term. Can it be saved? Some contributors to Is Social Justice Just? see social justice as envy dressed up in progressive rhetoric. Others argue that, although the term social justice has certainly been hijacked by envy and resentment, we need not jettison the term outright. True social justice is pro-liberty, pro-human flourishing and perfectly in line with the classical liberal understanding of justice as such. Though all twenty-one contributors have a different understanding of what, exactly, social justice ought to be, all think the term can be rescued and rehabilitated only if it is made to stand on legitimate principles (see below).
- In thinking about justice, social or otherwise, we must first consider the sources of inequality. Its obvious that inequality exists and that it can cause rifts in societies. Its not obvious how the government should address those rifts ... or if it should address them at all. How does one, for instance, propose to know the source, or sources, of inequality? And is the government best-equipped to confront that source(s)? We know that at least some inequality is the result of forces beyond any given generations control. Is it the governments role to remedy what (lets call it) fate has handed us? Could government do so effectively, even if it wanted to? Still more, inequality is the result of choice. Should the government enter the fray and limit human choice, in the name of justice? Is Social Justice Just? interrogates these claims, bringing the wisdom of ancient and modern philosophers to shed light on these perennial human questions.
- Involving the government in the mission of social justice is generally a bad, inefficient idea. All twenty-one contributors agree on one thing: more often than not, even the most honest attempts of the government to implement social justice rapidly decay into a base version of what economists call rent-seeking. Too many humanitarian schemes end up funding grift and reckless cronyism; resources, opportunities, and honor go to those with political sway, not those with true desert. But pursuing social justice can still be good for society ... and some authors in this nuanced volume even argue that the government is necessary in some cases. Still, Is Social Justice Just? largely explores how individualsnot governmentscan and should work toward a better world for themselves and their fellow man.
Synopsis
As Dr. Jordan B. Peterson points out in his foreword, the social justice warrior of our time insists on diversity of every kind, except diversity of outcome. But how can we accommodate diversity of every kind and insist on equal outcomes for all parties? Is Social Justice Just?, edited by Robert M. Whaples, Michael C. Munger, and Christopher J. Coyne, presents a series of essays that lay bare the vacuity of these ideas, without dismissing the importance of justice as such.
One theme rings clearly throughout the volume: government-run efforts to implement social justice are at best woefully inefficient, at worst destructive. Most contributors agree with Friedrich Hayeks assertion that social justice is a kind of mirage, a misguided, incoherent concept that falsely claims society ought to conform to a predetermined just pattern. And yet, each author takes seriously those claims of social justice that have captured the modern imagination. The authors respond, earnestly and rigorously, not only to claims about monetary redistribution, but also to claims about institutions, privilege, societal relationships, the role of the state in securing justice, and more.
As readers page through Is Social Justice Just?, a resounding consensus comes to the fore. The term social justice can never assume a legitimate role in public discourse unless and until it stands on sound principles. And the first of these principles is mans inherent dignity and the liberty that flows from that dignity. With ample evidence from real-world experiences, lessons from history, the wisdom of the classics, the modern philosophers, and even the teachings of the world religions, the contributors of Is Social Justice Just? present an invaluable analysis of justice that illuminates the central role of the individual in achieving justice in all its aspects, including its social one.
Social Justice Gone Wrong
In todays world, the term social justice has been hijacked by the ideological left. Of course, that doesnt mean there is no such thing as social justice, nor does it mean social justice isnt important. That said, it does mean that misconceptions, abuses, and naïve uses of the term ought to be addressed first.
After a foreword by Jordan Peterson and a preface by Nicholas Rescher, Daniel Guerriere kicks off the discussion. A harsh critic of modern social justice, Guerriere argues that todays self-proclaimed social justice advocates care more about remaking human consciousness than being either social or just. Modern social justice, Guerriere argues, threatens to undo the discovery, protection, and promotion of the uniqueness of the individual, one of the greatest achievements of Western civilization. Citing the ancient Greeks, Hebrews, and Romans, Guerrieres critical takedown of modern social justice is as harsh as it is compelling.
R. Scott Smith focuses less on the stakes and more on the specific flaws of the modern social justice movement. He asserts that the key assumption of modern social justice is nominalism, the theory that only particular things exist and that there are no real, universal, identical, or shareable qualities between things. Even ethics, in this modern view, are nominalwhich means one cannot recognize by reason what is just or unjust. Consequently, power is the only force capable of backing ethical claims. Thus, ironically, the modern social justice movement cannot hope to give us social justice or any other kind of justice, since it depends on power (not reason) to establish reality.
In the following essay, Adam G. Martin takes us into the psyche of todays social justice advocate. Martin claims that todays warriors are animated by a spirit of resentment, which disguises itself in the language of social justice. Jacob T. Levy follows Martins analysis with the intellectual history of this inclination, pointing to John Rawlss Theory of Justice, which posited that social justice ought to address not only poverty, but also racism, sexism, and similar cultural phenomena. Levy points out that, unfortunately for Rawls, many injustices cannot be remedied. Thus, the Rawlsian vision of social justiceembraced by virtually all modern leftistshas bitten off more than it can chew.
Daniel J. DAmico continues Levys critique of Rawls. According to DAmico, the Rawlsian conception of social justice wrongly implies that one can move from democratic deliberation to positive social outcomes in a straight line. However, DAmico points out, vast knowledge problems lurk behind a veil of ignorance that make such a straight line impossible. In this way, DAmico shows how naïve Rawlss thinking really is. William Watkins Jr. shifts the spotlight from John Rawls to Ronald Dworkin, another popularizer of social justice as we know it today. Dworkin shows no hesitation in elevating unelected and unaccountable judges to the apex of the political order. He places the people, their representatives, and fundamental laweach, in its own way, a check on powerunder the feet of those judges, who are thus made all-powerful. Judges are now equipped, not to see that each man get his due but to ensure that society conform to their notions of fairness. Do we want to live under such a regime?
Finally, Anthony Gill concludes this section on social justice gone wrong with a discussion of economics. Gill notes that todays social justice advocates assert that gains from trade between a buyer and a seller can and ought to be equal. But this seemingly benign assertion is highly problematic, not only on the grounds of justice, but also on the important, irreducible grounds of preference, competition, and uncertainty. Readers will discover that there are many ways to do social justice wrong. But in each analysis, the contributors of Is Social Justice Just? emphasize the perennial problems of human nature: ignorance, resentment, and hubris.
Social Justice Gone Right
Its true that the term social justice has been hijacked, abused, and levied for destructive purposes. But it does not follow that social justice, rightly understood, should be dismissed. Prominent philosophers and theologians have concerned themselves with justice and mans relation to it since ancient times. We, too, can and ought to ask such questions. We may yet discover answers that alleviate our present condition.
James Stoner suggests, for instance, that a restoration of Aristotelian and Thomistic anthropology should serve as the basis for a modern conception of social justice. A limited state, however, is central to this vision; the family and civil society must be allowed to flourish without the heavy hand of government interference. John A. Moore shares this belief, insisting that true social justice is a bottom-up phenomenon, with individuals taking responsibility for themselves and for their neighbors. Martin Schlag, like Moore, cites the Roman Catholic Churchs social teachings on this subject. Noting that Pope Francis uses the term preferential option for the poor instead of social justice, Schlag insists that Franciss cultural revolution places the human personnot moneyat the center of social justice. Thus, only the faithful human person can combat the material and spiritual poverty of our time and do social justice right. D. Eric Schansberg agrees but adds that helping the poor on a voluntary basis is laudable from a Christian perspective, but that state-coerced redistribution of wealth violates the Eighth Commandment, Thou shalt not steal.
Pascal Salin offers a practical perspective on how to do social justice right. Arguing for the merits of inequality, Salin insists that human dignity derives from human differencesi.e., human inequalities. The fact that profits happen to result from these differences is not evidence of injustice, but of the condition for social cooperation between people. Andrew Jason Cohen continues in this vein, celebrating human differences and arguing that unregulated marketswhich necessarily feature human inequalitybring more wealth for all. If inequality is the price to pay for a dramatic reduction of absolute poverty, so be it! Axel Kaiser follows Cohens essay with a presentation of the economic science that proves competitive markets and limited governments are most beneficial to underprivileged societies.
But in our time, one must consider government action that will free markets and improve life for all, if only as a matter of prudence. To this end, Vincent J. Geloso and Phillip W. Magness present a much less hostile analysis of todays modern social justice movement. In their view, classical liberals should admit that lesser outcomes for certain groups have become too obvious to ignore. True believers in social justice must work to dismantle both formal and informal barriers to those forms of equality that are necessary for justice to occur. Racism, for example, must be expressly addressed. Stefanie Haeffele and Virgil Henry Storr follow this line of thinking, going so far as to critique Hayeks contention that social justice is merely a mirage. If it is a mirage, they ask, then why are some players in the marketplace clearly favored, by those claiming to be neutral referees, over others? To say such a situation is not unjust is flatly dishonest.
Finally, Dr. Robert Whaples, one of the editors of Is Social Justice Just?, concludes the collection by earnestly answering a question haunting all social justice advocates today: how can one justly combat racism? Contrasting his thesis with Ibram Kendis argument in How to Be an Antiracistwhich advocates scrapping capitalism entirelyWhaples suggests a range of antiracist policies that actually will contribute to social justice. Scrapping capitalism is not the answer. And yet, as Whaples concludes his sensible list of policy recommendations, he reminds readers that justice, in whatever form, is a matter that goes beyond governmental policy. It requires us to recognize that we are created to love one another as children of the same God.