In Phishing for Phools; The Economics of Manipulation and Deception, Nobel Prize-winning economists George Akerlof and Robert Shiller argue that free-markets are less benign than generally understood, because our free-market system tends to spawn manipulation and deception (p. vii). The phishing of the books title is not internet fraud to trick personal information out of people. The authors use it as a broad metaphor for getting people to do things that are in the interest of the phisherman, but not in the interest of the target (p. xi). Those targets are phools; psychological phools who let emotions...override the dictates of common sense or let cognitive biases...lead him to misinterpret reality (p. xi) and informational phools subject to manipulation and deception due to a lack of relevant knowledge. Phishing for Phools insists such phools become prey, because free markets inevitably create more phishermen whenever profitable phishing opportunities remain unexploited.
Phishing for Phools claims to be a very serious book (p. 11) and it makes sweeping claims of omnipresent phishing (though it backs away from some of its apocalyptic rhetoric later in the book), including Insofar as we have any weakness in knowing what we really want, and insofar as such a weakness can be profitably generated and primed, markets will seize the opportunity to take us on in those weaknesses (p. x) and Civil society and social norms do place some brakes on such phishing, but in the resulting market equilibrium, if there is an opportunity to phish, even firms guided by those with real moral integrity will usually have to do so in order to compete and survive (p. xii).
Unfortunately, the books analysis and the dire picture it paints are seriously flawed. Even applications intended to illustrate it actually contradict it.
Phishing for Phools starts from assertions that people do not do what is really good for them; they do not choose what they really want (p. 1) and that we follow monkey-on-our-shoulder tastes which are not good for us (p. 4). However, it never makes clear what those statements mean. Is what is good for us the same as what we really want? Does every choice the authors believe is not good justify added government regulations? Would beneficiaries really be grateful? And with regard to the volumes opening illustration, is every Cinnabon customer phished into a self-deluded choice? Such lack of clarity provides one reason its sweeping conclusions are insufficiently supported.
Phishing for Phools also errs in personifying markets as causing phishing, as when it asserts The free-market system exploits our weaknesses automatically (p. 3). Markets dont cause phishing. Self-interest and the willingness of some to take advantage of others spawn manipulation and deception, not free markets. In fact, the argument has causation reversed. The important issue is not that markets make people more ethical (though they do reward many types of such behavior), but that the more people find ways to reduce unethical behavior (the more people tell the truth, live up to agreements, etc.), the more efficient and beneficial markets become (as illustrated in economics textbook discussions of the superiority of legal markets over black markets). If the authors had studied, say, Avner Greifs work on the Maghribi traders (see "Contract Enforceability and Economic Institutions in Early Trade: The Maghribi Traders' Coalition," American Economic Review, Vol. 83, No. 3 (Jun., 1993), pp. 525-548), who made great strides in those areas, including against government depredations, they could have found both theoretical and empirical reasons to recognize this error.
Further, one cannot blame markets for enabling bad behavior because voluntary arrangements havent eliminated all bad behavior. Every form of social organization must deal with such hard facts about humanity. The relevant issue is whether other arrangements, such as those imposed by government (the primary institutional alternative to voluntary agreements) will produce less harm.
Unfortunately, rather than overcoming peoples self-interested willingness to bend others to their purposes, government often provides the means for them to impose greater harm. Governments comparative advantage is in coercion, which is both the most powerful form of manipulation and an incentive for greater deception, by raising the payoff to controlling it. Further, transferring owners decisions to government moves them to people with less productive information and worse incentives, selected through a political process that similarly attenuates voters information and incentives (as the authors admit, politics is vulnerable to the simplest phish (p. xvi)). And the understanding of even such basic issues of price controls, trade restrictions, and barriers to entry offers reason for industrial-strength skepticism of claims that government interventions will benefit citizens.
The authors also generate their dire pronouncements from the assertion that economic theory assumes businessmens behavior is purely selfish and self-serving (p. vii). That is not true. Economists assume people are self-interested, rather than selfish (see Gary Galles, Self Interested, Not Selfish, Mises Daily, https://mises.org/library/self-interest-not-selfishness). That is, we all desire command over more resources to advance things we care about, but there is no assumption of selfishness (e.g., actions such as Mother Teresa building a leprosarium with her Nobel Prize money are not ruled out). Economics assumes that our other-directed tastes are given, not non-existent. Here, Phishing for Phools is channeling game theorists who assume selfishness to make their models tractable, not because economics postulates it.
The books selfishness assumption is combined with the assertion that the fundamental concept of economics is the notion of market equilibrium (p. 1). That pairing is taken to imply that if one party did not phish you, someone else would, so that The free-market system exploits our weaknesses automatically (p. 3). In other words, The free-market equilibrium generates a supply of phishes for any human weakness (p. 22), a phishing equilibrium in which every chance for profit more than the ordinary will be taken up (p. 2).
This misstates economics actual foundation, which is scarcity. Scarcity implies individuals face incentives to alter choices so long as their expected marginal benefits exceed their expected marginal costs (an inequality indicating a person is not in equilibrium). Equilibrium is just a shorthand means to describe the direction market arrangements will adjust, expressed as a stopping rule when incentives to change behavior (disequilibrium) would cease, but in a world of uncertainty, change and frictions, people cannot be assumed in equilibrium. (Students of Austrian economics, in particular, will be sensitive to this confusion. As Peter Boettke has written [The Austrians on Equilibrium: Some Divergent Views, austrianomnibus.blogspot.com/2011/03/austrians-on-equilibrium-some-divergent.html], For Mises, however, equilibrium signifies the destruction of the science of economics (i.e. human action).
In addition, when individuals have moral beliefs and ethical commitments (i.e., they arent purely selfish), as is true of virtually every individual, it destroys the implication that equilibrium requires that every profitable phish will be undertaken. That is because people are not indifferent to how profits are earned. Many are willing to accept lower returns, when they consider the means ethical, over a normal rate of return earned unethically, which would include phishing, so there is no necessary zero-profit result to force markets into a phishing equilibrium.
Further, the books extension of the assumption that market equilibrium requires that every profitable opportunity be exploited to phishing ignores another implication of its logic that undermines its conclusions. If phishing is recognized as harmful, then providing anti-phishing protection will also be a profit opportunity for entrepreneurs. That would mean that every phish we can discover how to stop at a cost less than the benefit of stopping it will be stopped. And many of those means are yet to be discovered, so a successful phishing expedition today may soon become an unsuccessful one, solved by entrepreneurs. Consequently, the authors phishing tales that ignore anti-phishing profit incentives vastly overstate the harms involved.
After Phishing for Phools many alarming pronouncements, Chapter 11, The Resistance and Its Heroes, backs away from them because of individuals who step back from the profit incentive, who demonstrate that in fact we live in a community of people who care about one another (p. 136). In stark contrast to the books previous presentation, Businessmen of conscience with good products have both moral and economic reasons to out the phishermen (p. 140), implying that the phishing is everywhere warnings were dramatically and misleadingly overstated. And getting to this its not so bad point by first misstating economic theorys assumptions, then undoing the strawman several chapters later, will justifiably make many readers feel phished by the book, which is only made worse when it does another u-turn and returns to assertions of the inevitability of phishing (p. 170).
Chapter 11 also argues that we have reduced phishing by isolating information phishing to an outback of the hard-to-measure/ hard-to-evaluate (p. 137). If information phishing is largely contained, why go to all the effort to lump it in with psychological phishing, only to conclude they are not really similar and one of them isnt really a big problem? Again, readers will feel phished.
Phishing for Phools reflects other shortcomings, as well. They include an almost total absence of discussion of powerful market capitalization mechanisms (it decries supposed reputation mining but otherwise ignores the crucial role good reputations play in economic arrangements see W. Bentley MacLeod, "Reputations, Relationships, and Contract Enforcement," Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. 45, No. 3 (Sep., 2007), pp. 595-628); misrepresenting Adam Smith; frequent use of strawman arguments; and blaming free markets for phishing when ineffective government performance of its protective function is actually at fault. Perhaps even more important, though, is that in its eagerness to scapegoat free markets, it simply overlooks the fact that the government protectors it extols as solutions to phishing are actually among its primary causes.
One striking illustration is the books discussion of the mortgage meltdown, which it blames on various private actors. However, the mortgage market is not a free market, but a heavily and ineffectively regulated one. The book ignores government barriers to entry protecting existing credit rating firms from competition that would have produced more accurate assessments. It overlooks the role of the Department of Housing and Urban Developments increasing requirements for loans to lower income homebuyers. It also fails to notice that Fannie Mae and Freddy Macs willingness to buy bundles of bad loans as if they were good loans provided reassurance to other buyers because they anticipated they could always sell to a government-sponsored enterprises greater fool.
Perhaps the best illustration of the extent to which Phishing for Phools misrepresents reality, however, is its discussion of Social Security (pp. 153-55) as a QED illustration of its analysis which is preceded by a section lauding the Age of Reform, including populism, good-government progressivism and New Deal experimentalism, and a mythical post-WWII consensus that government would be a useful counterweight to the excesses of free markets, (p. 151) so that any attempt to argue government is the problemis itself a phish for phools (p. 152).
Phishing for Phools dismisses individuals competence to manage their own retirement because careful planning is psychologically difficult (p. 153). Then it lauds the good things Social Security and Medicare have done for certain groups. Unfortunately, it fails to recognize that all those accomplishments came about as the result of historys largest-ever financial phish. Social Security (including Medicare) has been a series of Ponzi schemes from the beginning (see Gary Galles, The Government Runs the Ultimate Ponzi Scheme, Mises Daily, https://mises.org/library/government-runs-ultimate-racket). Its origin and every expansion provided benefits far in excess of costs to early participants, requiring that later generations had to be forced to bear the burdens. It was promoted by conning voters into believing they had earned their benefits, which were absolutely guaranteed, yet the government argued that the taxes involved were actually available for the general support of government in Helvering v. Davis (1937) and that there were no benefit guarantees in Fleming v. Nestor (1960). The result is unfunded liabilities in Social Security and Medicare that are several times the official national debt (see Michael Tanner, Medicare and Social Security Tabs Coming Due Reason, March 2015).
Yet Phishing for Phools rejects privatization possibilities as to be blunt, daffy(p. 155), on the basis of a half-page summary of some simulations by one of the authors that (as far as I can tell) ignores not only Social Securitys unfunded liabilities, but also the welfare costs and the labor supply effects its taxes impose. However, a great deal of research by Edgar Browning (see, for example, The Anatomy of Social Security and Medicare, The Independent Review, Summer 2008) and others shows that trying to maintain the current unsustainable system is actually the daffy possibility.
In sum, Phishing for Phools has many phlaws, ranging from phaulty premises to internal inconsistencies and a blindness to evidence that is hard to see as unintentional. That makes it a poor investment. Phishing for Phools provides confusion, but few benefits that go beyond age-old warnings to Be careful, someone might try to take advantage of you. Many consumer advocates offer far more practical help. And they wont undermine your ability to spell for no good reason.
GARY M. GALLES Pepperdine University
Other Independent Review articles by Gary M. Galles | ||
Summer 2021 | The Big Government We Love to Hate: Exploring the Roots of Political Malaise | |
Fall 2020 | Charter Schools and Their Enemies | |
Spring 2020 | Do Markets Corrupt Our Morals? | |
[View All (5)] |